How America's top court justifies affirmative action

The Economist explains

How America's top court justifies affirmative action

FIFTY years ago, President Lyndon Johnson spoke of the need for affirmative action in an address at Howard University. “You do not”, Mr Johnson told the graduates, “take a person who, for years, has been hobbled by chains and liberate him, bring him up to the starting line of a race and then say, ‘You are free to compete with all the others,’ and still justly believe that you have been completely fair.” This race metaphor—along with the image of “leveling the playing field”—continue to animate debates about racial preferences in hiring and education a half-century later. But curiously, these justifications for giving special consideration to certain applicants have little to do with how America’s Supreme Court has addressed the question. And in their most recent foray into the constitutionality of affirmative action, Fisher v University of Texas, the justices seem flummoxed by their own jurisprudence. 
The Supreme Court has never said that race-conscious admissions policies may be used as tools to redress racial inequality per se. When, in 1978, the justices announced that racial identity may be examined as one factor among many in sorting through applications, they said that “preferring members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethnic origin is discrimination for its own sake”. The only legitimate justification for keeping an eye on race, Justice Lewis Powell wrote in Regents v Bakke, is the state’s compelling interest in “the educational benefits that flow from an ethnically diverse student body.” What are those supposed benefits? The Bakke court describes them as an “atmosphere of ‘speculation, experiment and creation’” that is “essential to the quality of higher education”. Heterogeneity of race and ethnicity contributes to a “robust exchange of ideas” in the classroom. And diversity has a broader impact outside the university’s gates. “It is not too much to say”, Justice Powell wrote, “that the ‘nation's future depends upon leaders trained through wide exposure’ to the ideas and mores of students as diverse as this nation of many peoples”. This wider point was developed 25 years later in Grutter v Bollinger, a 2003 case in which the court upheld the admissions policy at the University of Michigan law school. In addition to a richer classroom discussion, the Grutter court held, diversity promotes “cross-racial understanding and the breaking down of racial stereotypes”.
In questioning the lawyer defending the race-conscious admissions regime at the University of Texas last week, several justices took a rather blinkered view of these benefits. Chief Justice John Roberts seemed to presume that diversity is only about rich discussions. “What unique perspective”, he asked, “does a minority student bring to a physics class?” And in a rejoinder to Solicitor General Donald Verrilli, who noted that “our military leaders believe that it is imperative that we have officer corps that are not only diverse but capable of leading a diverse military”, Justice Samuel Alito missed the point when he asked whether minority students admitted through a top-percentage plan “make inferior officers” compared to those accepted under a race-conscious policy. The Grutter rationale says that classroom diversity serves people of all races by giving them a chance to get to know each other in a context where “the path to leadership [is] visibly open to talented and qualified individuals of every race and ethnicity”. Integrated schools, Justice Sandra Day O'Connor wrote in that case, “better prepare students for an increasingly diverse workforce [and] for society”. In order to pass constitutional muster, an affirmative action policy must pursue benefits for all students, and for society writ large, rather than merely for those whose ancestors have been “hobbled by chains”.
Few would contest the value of different people working together productively in harmony and mutual understanding. But the evidence for the value of affirmative action is mixed. Richard Sander says that preferences can be bad for members of racial minorities by setting them up to fail at universities where they cannot compete. (This is the “mismatch” thesis that was rather inelegantly described in last week’s Fisher hearing by Justice Antonin Scalia.) Other researchers respond that it is a mistake to deprive underrepresented minorities of the “benefits of an elite education” and elite schools of the “benefits of the rich diversity” based on data showing weaker results for some students of colour. Students with lower academic credentials could be provided with “interventions” that could “mitigate any negative match effects”, suggest Peter Arcidiacono and Michael Lovenheim of the National Bureau of Economic Research.

Popular posts from this blog

Cha-Ching? Drake Is Still Raking

Katy Perry flaunts her slender curves in an itsy-bitsy bikini